Contact: nikhilrajgupta09@gmail.com

Love in the Supreme Ethics

Monday 14 November 2016

RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE



TABLE OF CONTENTS 
INTRODUCTION

1. RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND RELIGION
2. BACKGROUND OF THE PROBLEM OF RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE    
   2.1 PLOTINUS MYSTICISM: GOD IS INEXPRESSIBLE   
   2.2 MODERN EMPIRICISM: GOD TALK IS NOT NONSENSICAL
3. VARIOUS PERSPECTIVES ON RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE
    3.1 VIA NEGATIVE (MAIMONIDES)
    3.2 SYMBOLISM (PAUL TILLICH)
    3.3 MYTH (WILLIAM PADEN, RUDOLF BULTMANN AND JOHN HICK)
    3.4 MEANINGLESSNESS (A.J. AYER)
    3.5 FALSIFIABILITY (ANTHONY FLEW)    
    3.6 LANGUAGE GAME (LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN)
3.7  UNIVOCAL, EQUIVOCAL AND ANALOGY (THOMAS AQUINAS)
4. RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE IS MEANINGLESS COGNITIVE AND NON- COGNITIVE
5. PROPOSED SOLUTIONS TO THE PREDICAMENT
    5.1 VERIFICATIONALISM
    5.2 FALSIFICATIONISM 
       5.2.1 Three key responses to Flew’s paper
     5.2.1.1. R M Hare’s Parable
           5.2.1.2 Basil Mitchell’s Parable
6.2.1.3  John Hick’s Eschatological verification

6. SOLUTIONS TO THE PROBLEM OF RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE 
7. INTRINSIC ANALOGY AGAINST CONTEMPORARY CRITICISM
CONCLUSION

BIBLIOGRAPHY



 INTRODUCTION

When we speak about God, is it meaningful? This subject has been a dominant topic of investigation in the philosophic world of the 20th and 21st centuries. What determines the meaningfulness of language or beliefs? Can religious language be empirically verified or falsified? Should we treat religious language separately from other language-games?
The basic question behind the religious language debate is ‘what can be said about God?' The religious language debate is not concerned with whether or not God exists, or what God is like or why there is evil in the world. It is especially concerned with working out whether or not religious language means anything. On the one side of the debate, you have the centuries old tradition of religious believers who believe that you can speak and write about God, because God is a reality.
On the other side, are the Logical Positivists and those that they influenced who claim that statements about God have no meaning because they don't relate to anything that is factual or real? The problem of religious language also provides a test for philosophers of religion. If there is no suitable solution to the problem of religious language, huge discussions in the sphere of philosophy of religion will also be rendered incoherent. For example, philosophers of religion debate the nature of divine foreknowledge and human freedom. These claims about God would be rendered incoherent if human speech about God is incredible.
Thus, the problem of religious language is a philosophical problem that must be solved in order to provide a context for understanding claims about God in both the church and the academy. Therefore, this paper will address the qualifications of verifiability and falsification theories with an elucidated critiques of the two theories, and propose a plausible solution.

1.      RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND RELIGION
Some rudiments of relationship exist between language and religion. Attaining a religion includes to some degree learning a new terminology and syntax. It would be impossible to attain a religion without the medium of language. Because what is said may predominantly condition what can be thought, the use of such speech design will have subtle psychological effects on the speakers, tending to boundary what can be named and hence what can be thought. Therefore, religion and language are closely associated to each other. The connection that exists amid language and religion is such that empowers Language to be used for intra-group communication within religious settings. In this context, language functions to help sustain conventionality to religious values, beliefs and ritual practices. “Religious jargons that are uncommon outside a religious group may be expressed, syntax may become more formal or even archaic, and style of speaking- such as a particular cadence, resonance and intonation pattern that is characteristic of the group- may be adopted.
Religion is apparently universal in all human societies. Although religions may differ significantly from one society to another, they own certain feature in common as to warrant their being labeled religions. In the same vein, every human society possesses a language. Chomsky in Campbell has famously claimed that there are similarities in the structures of all languages that point to the existence of a “universal Grammar” or “deep structure.”
Language and religion are related in the sense of uniting their users. People who speak the same tongue are likely to be closer and friendlier than others who do not understand the language of communication. This is seen clearly where people of diverse dialects converge in a place. Religion has such a binding force among its votaries that sometimes supersede that of siblings. In fact, some Christian conservatives and Christian denominations address one another as ‘brother’, ‘sister’ or even ‘elder’.
Besides that language and religion relate positively, they also possess, by their nature, the capacities to be exploited for negative purposes. Manipulators of language and religion have used them in the past for the destruction of many lives. Language and religion can successfully be used to hide the truth from the people. They could be employed to cause confusion, disunity and war in the society. At no time is this achieved better other than when religious emotions or convictions are expressed through the language of the people by trusted “experts”. This is the power of religion and language. Most of the religious upheavals we have had in this country came to be through this way.

2.      BACKGROUND OF THE PROBLEM OF RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE
Most contemporary religious language theory vacillates between equivocation and analogy in a desperate struggle to provide a meaningful vehicle by which God can be expressed. The background of the problem is twofold: Medieval Mysticism and Modern Empiricism.

       2.1 Plotinus Mysticism: God is Inexpressible[1]
Plotinus is the fountainhead of negative theology. In him Greek rationalism culminated in Neo-Plotinus Mysticism. And through his Neo-Plotonic followers, Proclus and Dionysius the Middle Ages inherited a strong negative emphasis in language about God. The entire Politian system is based on the notion of unity.[2] All multiplicity is made up of unities, there must be a prior unity which is absolutely Simple (God). Plotinus was not totally unaware of the implications of a purely negative theology. Plotinus wrote:
It is impossible to say, ‘No that’ if not is utterly without experience or Conception of the ‘That’; there will generally have been, even, some inkling of the good beyond Intellection”. How positive “inklings” of God are possible when we know of Him is through extrinsic attribution known only negatively is not clear. The implication is that there is a positive intuition of god which enables us to from negative concepts of Him. One thing is clear, there is nothing in realm of concepts or language which is positively description of God. God is beyond all words.[3]
And since all thought and language involves multiplicity; God is beyond all reason words.[4] The only way God can be known is via ascending from the multiplicity of the sensible and intellectual worlds and becoming one with one in a mystical union.

         2.2 Modern empiricism: God talk is not nonsensical
Not very many non- mystics are convinced that a purely negative language really says anything about God. Every negation implies an affirmation. And a purely unknowable God is unworshipable. As Ludwig Feuerbach remarked, “The truly religious man can’t worship a purely negative being....Only when a man loses his taste for religion does the existence of God becomes one without qualities, unknowable God.”[5] At any rate, there is in addition to Mysticism the problem of Empiricism for many modern religious analysts. In Mysticism there is no way to speak positive about God, and in semantically Atheism there is meaningful way to speak about God whatsoever[6].

3.      VARIOUS PERSPECTIVES ON RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE
     3.1 Via negative (Maimonides)
Jewish philosopher Maimonides believed that God can only be recognized in negative attributes, an opinion grounded on two vital Jewish dogmas: that the existence of God must be accepted, and that it is prohibited to define God. Maimonides did not consider that God holds all of his attributes perfectly and without impairment; rather, he proposed that God lies outside of any human measures. For him, to say that God is powerful, for example, would mean that God's power is beyond worldly power, and unparalleled to any other power. In doing so, Maimonides tried to illustrate God's inexpressible nature and draw attention to the linguistic boundaries of describing God.

    3.2 Symbolism (Paul Tillich)
Paul Tillich insisted on the symbolic nature of God-talk, since nothing from our Empirical experience is literally true of the “Ground of Being” (God). Symbolic Language, that is, metaphors and the like, play a very vital function in religious language. Tillich himself recognized this, and forced to recognize that there must be at least one non-symbolic truth about God (namely He is “Being” or “Ground of Being”). For unless one knew that something was literally true, how could one know that everything else was not literally true (that is, symbolic)?[7] When the John the Baptist said, ‘Behold, the Lamb of God, who takes away the sin of the World’ he was employing symbolism. Tillich insists that Jesus himself is such a symbol, of Himself he is nothing.[8]
Tillich reformed his claim to say that the only non-symbolic statement about God is “the statement that everything speaks about God is symbolic.” But this asserted appears to be about statement rather than about God. Tillich resolution was to say that “God is being itself” is both symbolic and non-symbolic, i.e., a “boundary line” kind of assertion. By his use of the “boundary-line” concept, Tillich tries to say both that religious language “points beyond itself,” i.e., has an objective reference, and that it also symbolizes what it itself does as a religious symbol for the one who uses it.[9]
Therefore, no finite reality can express it directly and properly. Religiously speaking, God transcends his own name. [10] Whatever statements say about that which concern ultimately, whether or not call it God, has a symbolic meaning. Tillich the language of faith is the language of symbols. The fundamental symbol of our ultimate concern is God. That means that in the notion of God must distinguish two elements: the element of ultimacy, which is a matter of immediate experience and not symbolic in itself, and the element of concreteness, which is taken from our ordinary experience and symbolically applied to God.[11]
According to Tillich examination of the symbolic character religious language, like scientific language, has its own principle of validation and these are relative to the context in which such language appropriately may be used.[12] But it still remains to show more clearly how religious symbols can be tied in with this language of being and existence; and above all, how talk about particular beings or their properties can even indirectly refer to Being an illuminated for it.

            3.3 Myth (William Paden, Rudolf Bultmann and John Hick)
William Paden maintained that religious language uses myth to present truths through parables. He argued that to those who practice a religion, myths are not mere fiction, but provide religious truths. Lutheran theologian Rudolf Bultmann suggested that the Bible holds existential truths which is expressed through mythology. Bultmann sought to find the existential truths behind the veil of mythology, a task known as 'demythologising'. He supposed that God interacts with humans as the divine Word, perceiving a linguistic character inherent in God, which seeks to provide humans with self-understanding.[13] Bultmann believed that the cultural embeddedness of the Bible could be overcome by demythologising the Bible, a process which he believed would allow readers to better encounter the word of God.[14] As follower of Bultmann, Christian philosopher John Hick held that the language of the Bible should be demythologised to be compatible with naturalism. He offered a demythologised Christology, arguing that Jesus was not God incarnate, but a man with incredible experience of divine reality. To Hick, calling Jesus the Son of God was a metaphor used by Jesus' followers to describe their commitment to what Jesus represented.

          3.4 Meaninglessness (A.J. Ayer)
For A. J. Ayer religious language is as meaningless as it is considered not to be open to falsification and allows nothing in experience to count against belief in God. And any statement that is neither a tautology nor a statement of fact is meaningless and nonsensical. They are nonsensical in the senses that their senses or meaning is not obtainable by reference to sense – experience.[15]
Ayer agreed that since all statements about God cannot be verified, they are meaningless, but the notion of a person whose essential attributes are non-empirical is not intelligible notion at all. A word which is used as if it names this ‘person,’ (God) but, unless the sentences in which are empirically verifiable, it cannot be said to symbolize anything. Ayer identified and defended a “weak principle of verification,” in “The principle of verifiability.” He insisted that empirical propositions are not conclusively verifiable, but in order for a claim to be factual, and thus to have its truth value determined, it must be verifiable by some possible observations. While Ayer didn’t specify exactly what those possible observations must be, he argued that they need to be the kinds of observations that could verify an assertion.[16] Ayer says like this: A proposition is said to be verifiable, in the strong sense of the term, if and only if, its truth could be conclusively established in experience. But it is verifiable, in the weak sense, if it is possible for experience to render it probable. Ayer was the first logical positivist to focus provocatively the verificationist criterion of the meaning of factual statements upon theological affirmations. [17] Ayer argued that all religious language is non-sensical since none of it is empirically understandable .The criterion of logical positivism, in turn, has been proven to be non-sensical since it is itself empirically unproven .The best position regarding religious language seems to be the view of ‘forms of life’ according to which religious language is only understandable that those who share in the particular form of religious life.[18]
Furthermore, he does not demand that in order for a statement to be considered as having factual content it be conclusively verifiable or conclusively falsifiable. Nor will he accept the phenomena lists dictum that a physical- object statement is actually a statement about sense impressions. Ayer described that religious language according to the falsifications, does not belong to the domain of “genuine science.”  The religious talk of believers is ultimately meaningless. This is a necessary condition for a truly scientific approach to what rational men will believe.[19]

         3.5 Falsifiability (Anthony Flew)                                
Flew argues that “God” is too vague a concept to be meaningful. For if God’s greatness entails being invisible, intangible and inscrutable, then he can’t be disproved — but nor can he be proved. Such powerful but simply stated arguments made by Flew.[20]
While Ayer had attacked the meaningfulness of any claim to religious knowledge, Flew give a parable of a gardener:
Once upon a time two explorers came upon a clearing in the jungle. In the clearing were growing many flowers and many weeds. One explorer says, ‘some gardener must tend this plot.’ The other disagrees, there is no gardener, so they pitch their tents and set a watch, but nothing happens. The believing explorer still affirms his belief in a gardener, but suggests that the gardener is invisible. The two explorers set up an electrified barbed- wire fence and patrol it with bloodhounds. Still nothing happens. The wires never sway, and the bloodhounds never back. The gardener, so he argues, is invisible, intangible, and insensitive to electric shocks. He has no scent and makes no sound, but he loves and tends the garden. Finally, skeptic despairs and asks the believer how his gardener differs from no gardener at all.[21]
Flew argues that, in the same way, if a believer’s statement about God can be made to fit into any circumstance, it is not meaningful and has no empirical implications.[22] Because Flew presumes to establish meaningfulness on the basis of falsifiability, he can readily reduce three distinct statements of this parable to equivalent claims.[23] Since he attaches the same empirical expectations throughout, and no gardener is observable by various empirical tests (observation, electrified fencing and bloodhound patrol), Flew considers the sentences equally meaningless. Yet many critics have pointed out an underlying ambiguity in Flew’s three statements and that they actually convey distinguishable meanings. The first, “an invisible, intangible, eternally elusive gardener,” implies a non-empirical gardener, while the reference of the second to “no empirical gardener” may be taken to indicate “no gardener empirical or non-empirical.” Flew notes that the sentences to God for whom the invisible gardener stands in, but not in imaginary gardener. Flew declares that any belief that is compatible with all states of affairs is meaningless, that is, any belief is which is not falsifiable is nonsense. Flew’s insistence is that God-talk is in principle unfalsifiable.[24]

         3.6 Language Game (Ludwig Wittgenstein)
For Ludwig Wittgenstein, language was thought to possess an underlying logical positive to say that statements like ‘God is good’ are meaningless since they cannot be verified in reality, i.e., they don’t convey any meaningful information about reality when broken down to their simplest terms. However, later, Wittgenstein himself questioned this method and goal because of the paradox involved in trying to represent in language how language represented the world. In his philosophical investigation (1953) Wittgenstein established the many functions of language and of meaning as dependent on language game, use and forms of life.[25] The meaning of words may differ from context to context depending on the way they are used in each context, which Wittgenstein terms the ‘language game’ of the word. Similarly, the meaning of an understood by participation in the form of life pertaining to the world or language game in which a word finds its use and meaning. For instance or ‘honest’ and ‘lying’ have no role or function or use in the kind of life a dog leads and so the question it is incorrect to say that dogs do not since they are honest. Likewise, there are forms of life among humans that need to be understood in order to understand the words used therein.[26]
According to Wittgenstein language consists in part, then, of words, which in their simplest form refer to a particular thing and its predicate.[27] As Wittgenstein discussed just above how language links itself to the world, and his discussion of how language represents the world was itself expressed in language. This placed Wittgenstein in the paradoxical situation of having used language to represent how language represents the world. And this, he concluded could not be done, it Language, may be used to represent the world. “What expresses itself in language, it cannot express by means of language.” Language games exist within all forms of human activities and lives. He said people who are not in the game will not understand the use of the language and will find it meaningless to them. Religious belief has its own language and non-believers will find religious language meaningless as they are not in the religious "game." Problems develop when the language "goes on holiday." This is when words are used outside of their context and use ordinary language to describe God. The meaning of the word God applies to a being beyond human understanding.[28]

         3.7 Univocal, Equivocal and Analogy (Thomas Aquinas)
Thomas Aquinas thought that it was certainly possible to talk about God in a meaningful way. He isolated three forms of language. Univocal, equivocal and analogy. Aquinas posed concerning the use of finite concepts about an infinite God. Without initial meaning religious expectations could never be verified, for the identity of the predicated event or situation would remain unknown. And without a means of verification, the interpretation of one’s experience now as mediating God’s presence an interpretation which verification supposedly validates becomes pointless.[29] He said that religious language is the language of analogy is not enough. It has be shown that there is a genuine correspondence between language and its object. The problem is apparently made more acute by the fact that cannot step outside language and thought forms and see God directly, as he is in Himself, so that could test them. Even though, in the nature of the case, divine truth has to be refracted and expressed in terms of human words and finite images, nevertheless it can be expressed in meaningful terms.[30]
For Aquinas our language is properly applicable to worldly things, since our intellect abstracts concepts from material substances as they appear to sensory perception, and words stand for those concepts. God cannot be an object of sense, so how can our words apply to God? Aquinas points out that creatures are in a dependent relation to God as the cause of their existence, and that effects resemble their causes. God, as the source of the perfections found in creatures, can be spoken of through them as his effects. While causation is what enables to speak truly of God, is not limiting ourselves to referring to God's actions as distinct from His essence. Aquinas points out that religious people mean what they say in praising God for His goodness. Thanksgiving is not directed to an anonymous benefactor for the excellence of the creaturely goodness he supplies. God is the paradigm of the goodness, etc. that is held derivatively by creatures.[31]
Aquinas religious language often attempts to describe the attributes or qualities of God.   This is hard because God is generally not something direct experience of, whereas most of the things that language refers to are things that can be experience e.g. love, walking, etc,.  So when we describe ’God is good’, its need to know that is using ’good’ in that sentence.   In univocal terms, this would be claiming that God is good in some way that humans are, Aquinas rejected this as he believed God to be perfect.   Because of this, imperfect humans can’t be good in the same way that God is.   In equivocal terms, this would mean that God is good in a totally different way to humans, Aquinas rejected that too.[32] 

4.      RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE IS MEANINGLESS; COGNITIVE AND NON-COGNITIVE
In the debate about religious language, it is important that broadly speaking, there are two types of language, cognitive and non-cognitive. Cognitive language conveys facts i.e. things that we can know or be cognizant (The skyscraper is falling down, ‘Badgers have black and white fur). Non-cognitive language, predictably, conveys information that is not factual; emotions, feelings and metaphysical claims (The Lord upholds all who are falling, He fulfils the desire of all who fear him, and He also hears their cry and saves them). [33] Christian claims are not a special kind of religious fact. Though it is received by mystic it is still cognitive. They are the cognitive informational facts upon which all historical legal, and ordinary decisions are based.[34] Above you have examples of two very different types of language. On the left hand side is an excerpt from the Psalms, which talks about God and what he is supposed to be like. On the right hand side are statements of fact about things in the world. These two types of language are important for understanding the problems raised by the religious language debate.

5.      PROPOSED SOLUTIONS TO THE PREDICAMENT
Influenced by Karl Popper, Antony Flew applied the Falsification Principle to religious language and concluded that religious statements are nothing more than non-sensical utterances of little significance. As indicated above, the meaningfulness of religious language has come under attack in philosophical circles in two ways during this century. We need to look at each one of them. The first can be designated the "verificationist" challenge to religious discourse, and the second designated the "falsificationist" challenge. Neither has proven successful.

            5.1 Verificationalism
In the earlier part of this century a school of thought known as logical positivism zealously promoted empirical science and disparaged any kind of metaphysics. According to the positivists, any proposition could be tested for meaningfulness by applying to it the "verification principle." [35]
Logical positivism acknowledged two different kinds of meaningful sentences. Certain sentences in a language will be known to be true simply by means of analyzing them logically and linguistically (for instance: "all bachelors are unmarried" can be verified by reference to laws of logic and semantic definitions). However, such truths (called "analytical") are devoid of significant information about the world of experience or observation, and thus are trivial. The effect of applying the verification principle, the positivists concluded, would be the dismissal of all metaphysical claims (including theology) and all ethical claims as non-sense from a scientific standpoint.[36] Since the religious language of Christians is filled with terms which are not taken from observation (e.g., God, omnipotence, sin, atonement) and claims for which there is no empirical means of confirmation (e.g., God is triune, Jesus intercedes for the saints), logical positivism's verification principle seemed to rule out the meaningfulness of what Christians said.
A. J. Ayer was perhaps the best known logical positivist in the English world. In the first edition of his famous book, Language, Truth and Logic, Ayer maintained that a sentence is meaningful when, in conjunction with other premises, an observation statement can be deduced which could not have been derived from the other premises alone. This was entirely unhelpful. With a little imagination, a logician could use this criterion and show that any statement whatsoever can pass the test- in which case Ayer's criterion of verifiability allows all statements to count as meaningful! One way of establishing whether or not a statement is meaningful was proposed by A J Ayer.[37] This criterion for meaning was called the Verification Principle and insisted that for a statement to be meaningful, it must be verifiable by sense experiences – or, in the weaker form of the principle, it should be possible to know what sense experience could make the statement probable. But the principle was quickly discredited as an adequate criterion of meaning, and much recent philosophy has examined less narrow ways in which language is used. But it is difficult to abandon completely the notion that for a statement to be meaningful, it must in some sense be shown to correspond to reality.[38] However, later Ayer formulated his own, more liberal verifiability criterion. Known as ‘weak verifiability’, it asserts that a sentence has empirical import if ‘some experimental propositions (he later changed this phrase to ‘observation statements’) can be deduced from it in conjunction with other premises without being deducible from those other premises alone’. Both the verification and falsification principles were rejected as criteria of cognitive significance because they were too strict. Weak verifiability must also be rejected, but because it is too lax.[39]

           5.2 Falsificationism 
The falsificationists were dedicated to the authority of natural science, just like the logical positivists. However, the falsificationists were painfully aware of the failure of the logical positivists to formulate cogently, or save themselves from the fatal application of, the verification principle of meaning.[40]
Various implications of this notion were put to the test in a famous exchange that played out in the philosophical Journal University in the 1950s. The debate opened with a paper by Antony Flew which centred on an old parable of an invisible gardener. Flew’s point is a subtle one. The believer’s initial claim that a gardener must exist is tested in several ways, and each piece of evidence is dismissed by a qualification – the gardener is invisible, then intangible, then free of scent, and so on. By the end, there seems no way of testing the existence of the gardener at all. The claim seems empty of content and therefore meaningless. Taking his cue from Karl Popper, Flew argues that for a statement to be meaningful it must at least be open to falsification– there must be some way of showing it to be false.
For the falsificationist, what makes genuine science "scientific" is that the theories which it will affirm are in principle falsifiable by means of empirical methods. This is a necessary condition for a truly scientific approach to what rational men will believe. Accordingly, if some theory or claim is not empirically falsifiable, this defect alone is sufficient to dismiss it as being cognitively meaningless. A meaningful claim in science must be, according to the falsificationist, subject to refutation (in theory). This does not mean that scientific claims must be refuted in order to be "scientific" (which would make all scientific claims false by definition!) but that they must be empirically refutable in some conceivable circumstance.[41]
The great advantage of taking this approach, if you advocate the supremacy of natural science and its procedures, is that the generalizations after which the scientist aspires (e.g., "all planets rotate around an axis") are not ruled out as meaningless by virtue of their not being fully verifiable. The generalizations of natural science, even those which are true, will always be open to refutation or falsification (e.g., just in case we ever find a planet that does not rotate around an axis).[42] No longer is the incompleteness of induction a strike against the meaningfulness or scientific character of an empirical generalization concerning the natural world.

5.2.1        Three key responses to Flew’s paper
        5.2.1.1. R M Hare’s Parable
At first sight Hare’s paranoid lunatic seems to confirm Flew’s argument, and Hare agreed that religious statements are meaningless by Flew’s standards of evidence. But what counts as evidence? For the lunatic, there is plenty of evidence to confirm his paranoia: from his perspective, every ‘diabolical’ don’s mild manner is just a pretense. It is this notion of perspective that is key: Hare calls this a ‘blik’, a frame of reference that determines what counts as evidence. A ‘blik’ is a way of seeing the world, a filter that affects our standards of evidence. The paranoid man’s blik leads him to see evidence of hostility in everything; the religious blik similarly allows the believer to see evidence where a sceptic may not.
Hare’s point is that religious statements are not assertions at all, and therefore are immune to verification and falsification. Instead they are expressions of a particular blik with particular standards of explanation and conduct.[43] Religious people see the world a certain way, and from within that perspective all sorts of things count as evidence for God: a beautiful sunset, a flock of geese, the ‘miracle’ of birth, and so on.

 5.2.1.2 Basil Mitchell’s Parable
Mitchell’s partisan is certainly more flattering to believers than a paranoid lunatic, and the parable illustrates that belief in the absence of conclusive evidence is not unreasonable. While Flew insists upon empirical tests to render a statement meaningful, Mitchell shows that belief is as much a matter of trust and commitment. Religious claims do not have to be intellectually convincing: a believer can trust in their relationship with God, as the partisan comes to trust the stranger. Moreover the partisan’s trust is falsifiable in principle (and thus meets Flew’s challenge) but the question remains: what would it take to change the partisan’s mind? How much evidence is required to show that the stranger has betrayed him?[44] Mitchell admits that there is no simple answer to this question – but at least it is not unreasonable to give the stranger the benefit of the doubt.
5.2.1.3 John Hick’s Eschatological Verification
Responding to the verification principle, John Hick used his parable of the Celestial City to describe his theory of eschatological verificationism. His parable is of two travelers, a theist and an atheist, together on a road. The theist believes that there is a Celestial City at the end of the road; the atheist believes that there is no such city. Hick's parable is an allegory of the Christian belief in an afterlife, which he argued can be verified upon death. Hick believed that eschatological verification is "unsymmetrical" because while it could be verified if it is true, it cannot be falsified if not. This is in contrast to ordinary "symmetrical" statements, which can be verified or falsified.[45]
In other words, religious claims may, in the end, be verifiable if true (although not falsifiable if false). Hick’s point is that the two men experience the journey differently: the believer accepts the good and the bad calmly and pursues the path in hope of salvation. Belief makes a difference. It is important to note that Hick is not claiming that religious statements are true (or false), only that they are meaningful and that belief in those statements is reasonable. This approach has become known as eschatological verification.

6.      SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF RELIGIOUS LANGUAGE
Multiple solutions have been suggested and defended over time. Three of these will be briefly mentioned.
·         The first solution suggests that all attributes predicated of God are to be interpreted equivocally, with respect to what they mean in reference to creatures. Consequently, this solution would argue that god is not good in the same sense Mother Theresa was; god’s goodness is entirely different from the goodness of a creature. However, god can be spoken of by human beings only through negations.
·         The second solution suggests that the attributes predicated of god are to be interpreted univocally. A modern proponent of this view is Alton. He argues that a human being can know something and god can know that same fact. But how god knows something will be different from the way that a human being knows in so far as god incorporeal omniscient etc.
·         The third solution suggests that the attributes predicated of god are to be interpreted analogously. For instance, when the predicate good is applied to God, good refers to the unity that is god’s essence and not an individual feature of God. This approach provides a middle position between an equivocal and a univocal solutions, since terms used analogously are not entirely equivocal nor are they entirely univocal: terms used analogously signify the same thing but in different modes (Aquinas). Even Norman Geisler, a renowned Christian philosopher is a modern proponent of this view.
7.      INTRINSIC ANALOGY AGAINST CONTEMPORARY CRITICISM
An intrinsic analogy is one in which both things possess the same characteristics, each in accordance with its own being. Intrinsic analogy is based on the similarity of relations.  Analogy is based on an alleged ontological similarity between God and the world. Theism pleads guilty of this charge and offers two lines of evidence.
First, the Bible teaches that creation does reflect and reveal its Creator (Ps. 19:1; Rom. 1:19-20; Acts 17:28, 29). Man was made in God’s “image and likeness” (Gen. 1:27).
Secondly, an analogy of being is based in the causal connection between the Creator and His creatures. God’s work, like that of other artists, resembles the Artist. Being is defined the same way for God and creatures, “that which is or exist.”[46]
God exists and creatures exist; herein is the similarity. But God exists infinitely and independently, whereas creature exist finitely and dependently; herein is the difference.[47]
Therefore, the fact of existence is the same for both God and creatures but the mode of existence is different.
That is the concept of being is univocal but being itself is analogous. Therefore, that whenever adding the qualifier “infinite “ totally negates the univocal concept of perfection, then it tells us nothing about God’s essence but at best something about His activity.
  
CONCLUSION
The claim that language referring to God is meaningless has become virtually a dead issue. This does not mean, however, that the use of language to speak about God is unproblematic. Internally, within the religious language-game and form of life, universal claims and pronouncements can still be made.[48]
In contemporary times attention has shifted to how such statements could be verified or falsified scientifically. Real life experiences show belief or faith to be a reality. Therefore, its expression which essentially must contain predicate about God and his nature, as a matter of fact, should have meaning at least to the group of people who use such language.
The essence of using a language is to communicate. Religious languages communicate and express ideas, emotions and convictions to faith audience. It is the medium for the transmission of religious ideas between faith members.
The end purpose of this expression and communication of religious ideas and emotions is to elicit acts that are similar to what is expressed and communicated in order to gain eternal life. This is why the expression of religious language, together with its meaning could be linguistically okay but religiously incomplete without the accompanying religious-behavioral commitment. Analogy is not only important in ordinary language and common sense, but also in science, philosophy and humanities.
In the end, as Aquinas inferred unless there is an analogy of being based in the created similarity of God and the world, then we cannot avoid either Monism or equivocation in talking about God’s essence. In summation, equivocal predication leads to skepticism; univocal predication leads to Monism, but only analogical predication leads to God. Ultimately, the analogy theory attempts to avoid this dilemma about terms referring to both God and creation, by altering their meaning in each case. So while there is something in the meaning of terms common to God and man creature which is the same, there is also something very different.
In this way both wholly univocal and wholly equivocal meanings for these terms are avoided, and the analogy is established. Thus the theory ends up claiming that what God really possesses is the highest degree of (some of) the qualities which creatures possess a degree not in creation at all.











[1] Norman Geisler, “Analogy: The Only Answer to the Problem of Religious Language,” http;//www.religious forms.com/forum/articles/60015-religious-language.htm/ (accessed on 19/07/15).

[2] Sallie McFague, Metaphorical Theology: Models of God in Religious Language (USA: Fortress Press, 1982), 1.
[3] Norman Geisler, “Analogy: The Only Answer To The Problem Of Religious Language,” http;//www.religious forms.com/forum/articles/60015-religious-language.htm/ (accessed on 28/07/14).
[4] Nile Green and Mary Searle-Chatterjee (eds) Religion, Language, and Power (USA: Library of Congress, 2008), 72.
[5] Roger M. White, Talking about God: The Concept of Analogy and the Problem of Religious Language (UK: British Library, 2010), 7.
[6]Geisler, “Analogy: The Only Answer To The Problem Of Religious Language. (Accessed on 28/07/14).
[7] Norman L. Geisler, Introduction to Philosophy: A Christian Perspective (Michigan: Grand Rapids, Baker Book House, 1980), 307-308.
[8] Colin Brown, Philosophy: The Christian Faith (Illinois: Inter Varsity Press, 1968), 197.
[9] Milton D. Hunnex, Chronological and Thematic Charts of Philosophies and Philosophers, (Michigan: Grand Rapids, Zondervan publishing house, 1961), 34.
[10] Stanley N. Gundry, Tensions In Contemporary Theology (Chicago: Moody Press, 1976), 87.
[11] Paul Tillich, Symbols of Faith: Excerpted from Dynamics of Faith (New York: Harper& Row, 1957), 72.
[12] Allie M. Frazier, Issues in Religion (2nd edn.) (California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1975), 275.
[13] Louis P. Pojman, Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology. (California: Wadsworth, 2008), 21.

[14] Anthony Campbell, Religion, Language, Narrative and the Search for Meaning (Lulu, 2009), 81-82.

[15] Domenic Marbaniang, Epistemic of Divine reality (n.p), 2007, 149.
[16][n.a.], “Religious language”, http://www.sevenoaksphilosophy.org /religion/religiouslanguage.htm// (accessed on 29 November 2014).
[17]Stanley Gundry, Tensions In Contemporary Theology, 128.
[18]Domenic Marbaniang, Theology and Philosophy of Religion, [n.p], 2011, 12.
[19]  Roy Clouser, Religious language: http://www.freewebs.com/royclouser/religious%20language  (accessed on 29/07/14).
[20] Anthony Flew, “Religious language” http://www.nytimes.com/2007/11/04/magazine/04Flew-t.html?pagewanted=all&_r=0 (accessed on 29/07/14).).
[21] Norman L Geisler, Introduction to philosophy: A Christian perspective. (Michigan: Grand Rapids, Baker Book House, 1980), 60.
[22] Geisler, Introduction to Philosophy, 61.
[23]Mark Webb, A Comparative Doxastic-Practice Epistemology of Religious Experience (New York: Library of Congress, 2011), 11-13.
[24] Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, 106.
[25] Garth L. Hallett, Theology within the Bounds of Language: A Methodological Tour (New York: State University, 2011), 46.
[26]Marbaniang, Epistemics of Divine Reality, 42.
[27] Samuel Enoch Stumpf, Socrates to Sartre: A History of Philosophy (4thedn.), (New York: McGraw-Hill, Inc, 1988), 453.
[28][n.a], “Religious Language” http://www.markedbyteachers.com/as-and-a-level/religious-studies-and-philosophy/religious-language-is-meaningless-discuss (accessed on 03/08/2015)
[29] Stanley N. Gundry, Tensions in Contemporary Theology (Chicago: Moody press, 1976), 139.
[30] Colin Brown, Philosophy: The Christian Faith. Illinois: Inter Varsity Press, 1968, 34.
[31][n.a], “Aquinas`s Account of The Naming of God: Investigating Thomas Aquinas`s doctrine of the analogical significance of religious language” http://www.tutorhunt.com/resource/6462/http://www.tutorhunt.com/resource/6462/ (accessed on 7/08/15).
[32][n.a], Religious Language:http://www.antiessays.com/free-essays/Religious-Language-Is-Meaningful 403227.html  (accessed on 7/08/15).

[33] John Macquarrie, Principles of Christian Theology (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1966), 123.
[34] Josh McDowell, Knowing Good from Evil (Illinois: Tyndale house publishers, 2002), 105.
[35] John Macquarrie, Principles of Christian Theology (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1966), 124.
[36] Louis P. Pojman, Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology. (California: Wadsworth, 2008), 34.

[37] Paul Tillich, Symbols of Faith: Excerpted from Dynamics of Faith. (New York: Harper& Row, 1957), 52.

[38] Harold H. Titus, Living Issues in Philosophy (8thedn.) (California: Wadsworth Publishing, 1986), 374.
[39] Bruce J. Caldwell, Beyond Positivism (New York: Taylor Press Group, 1982), 21.
[40] Greg Bahnsen, “The Problem of Religious Language(Part 1)” http://www.cmfnow.com/articles/pa146.htm (accessed on 09/08/15).
[41] [n.a.], “The Concept of Religious Language.” http;//www.crvp.org/book/series 01/I 28/chapter 3.htm (accessed on 09/08/15).
[42] H.E. Hofmeister, Truth and Belief: Interpretation and Critique of the Analytical Theory (Kulwer: Academic Publisher, 1990), 165.
[43] Roy A Clouser, “Divine Accommodation: An Alternative Theory of Religious Language,” //http//www.amn alternative-theory –of –religious- language/ (accessed on 22nd December 2014).

[44] [n.a.] “Religious Language” http://www.sevenoaksphilosophy.org/religion/religious-language.html (accessed on 09/08/15).
[45] (n.a.) “Religious Language” http://www.sevenoaksphilosophy.org/religion/religious-language.html (accessed on 19/07/15)
[46] Shepherd, “Aquinas - Language as Analogy.”
[47] Geisler, “Analogy”.
[48] William J. Wainwright, Philosophy of Religion (Milwaukee: University of Wisconsin, [n.y], 360.

0 comments: